Because some arguments are
impossible to model exhaustively—there is an infinite number of ways
the world in question could be—it is harder to show that these arguments are
true. Some such arguments are categorical ones. For instance, we could argue
that “All apples are fruits. Therefore, if everything is an apple, everything
is a fruit.” Even though this argument is clearly valid, there is no way to
model every world in which our premise is true. But if we make the argument: “All
apples are blue. Therefore, everything that is blue is an apple.” We could
imagine a world in which there is a pear and an apple, and they are both blue.
In this world, the argument is invalid, since every apple is blue, there is
something blue that is not an apple. (in fact, we don’t even need an apple in
our world to prove this argument is false.) As with our previous, simpler
arguments, a valid argument is one whose conclusion is true in every world in
which its premises are true. Thus, it is sufficient to show that the argument
does not hold in this one world to prove it invalid.
We could analyze arguments (and sentences in
general) more deeply by considering predicates as sets. Rather than considering
the predicate “x is an apple”, for example, we could simply have the set of all
things that are apples. Using the same method, we could state that “the set of
apples is a subset of the set of blue things” rather than “all apples are
blue”. Then, to show that our previous argument is invalid, we could imagine
that there are other elements in the set of blue things that aren’t apples. In
other words, these sets don’t have to be identical. This idea of subsets is a
very good one to use when you have more complicated arguments and works for
almost everything. It does, however, run into some problems. The most basic
problem comes in the form of a contradiction and can be derived from defining a
set through the predicate: “all sets that do not contain themselves”. If the
set does contain itself, then the predicate tells us that it must not contain
itself, and if the set does not contain itself, the predicate tells us that it
must. Another potential problem is infinitely telescoping—sets that are
infinitely large and contain themselves. For example, there is the set of all
sets that “contain more than one element”. This set has an infinite number of
elements, meaning that it must be a member of itself. Thus, not only does this
set have infinitely many subsets, but it contains a copy of itself, meaning
that it must have more elements than itself.
I found this post very interesting and thought provoking. It made me think about logic in a different way than I had ever done before, and made me re-examine the way I think about things.
ReplyDeleteNot going to lie, this post confused me ALOT. But I guess I'm just not logically thinking about it?
ReplyDelete