Skip to main content

Logic


Because some arguments are impossible to model exhaustivelythere is an infinite number of ways the world in question could be—it is harder to show that these arguments are true. Some such arguments are categorical ones. For instance, we could argue that “All apples are fruits. Therefore, if everything is an apple, everything is a fruit.” Even though this argument is clearly valid, there is no way to model every world in which our premise is true. But if we make the argument: “All apples are blue. Therefore, everything that is blue is an apple.” We could imagine a world in which there is a pear and an apple, and they are both blue. In this world, the argument is invalid, since every apple is blue, there is something blue that is not an apple. (in fact, we don’t even need an apple in our world to prove this argument is false.) As with our previous, simpler arguments, a valid argument is one whose conclusion is true in every world in which its premises are true. Thus, it is sufficient to show that the argument does not hold in this one world to prove it invalid.

                We could analyze arguments (and sentences in general) more deeply by considering predicates as sets. Rather than considering the predicate “x is an apple”, for example, we could simply have the set of all things that are apples. Using the same method, we could state that “the set of apples is a subset of the set of blue things” rather than “all apples are blue”. Then, to show that our previous argument is invalid, we could imagine that there are other elements in the set of blue things that aren’t apples. In other words, these sets don’t have to be identical. This idea of subsets is a very good one to use when you have more complicated arguments and works for almost everything. It does, however, run into some problems. The most basic problem comes in the form of a contradiction and can be derived from defining a set through the predicate: “all sets that do not contain themselves”. If the set does contain itself, then the predicate tells us that it must not contain itself, and if the set does not contain itself, the predicate tells us that it must. Another potential problem is infinitely telescoping—sets that are infinitely large and contain themselves. For example, there is the set of all sets that “contain more than one element”. This set has an infinite number of elements, meaning that it must be a member of itself. Thus, not only does this set have infinitely many subsets, but it contains a copy of itself, meaning that it must have more elements than itself. 

Comments

  1. I found this post very interesting and thought provoking. It made me think about logic in a different way than I had ever done before, and made me re-examine the way I think about things.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Not going to lie, this post confused me ALOT. But I guess I'm just not logically thinking about it?

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

Tomatoes

As a young child, I despised tomatoes. Unfortunately for me, however, my entire family was very fond of them. To my parent’s dismay, I would always decline when they offered me tomatoes in a sandwich or salad. It was hard for them to believe that tomatoes would render such a positive taste in their mouths, but not in a mouth engendered by them. Thus, they made it their goal to get me to like tomatoes; they were sure that my dislike for them was a fad that would soon wear off. They resorted to putting pureed tomatoes in my salads. But I outsmarted them: I would proceed to “disinfect” each individual piece of lettuce, each individual piece of cabbage, and each individual piece of spinach, with the precision of a neurosurgeon until there was no trace of tomato left on my salad. My hatred for tomatoes slowly became an integral part of my identity. I made friends and enemies over my opinions on tomatoes. During recess, I would sit on the bench and talk about tomatoes with my friends. Soon

Copa America

Brrrrriiiingg. My brother and I promptly jumped out of bed with excitement. it was going to be the first time we had ever attended a major sporting event. A Copa America final between Argentina and Chile being played only a few miles away from our aunt’s house. An opportunity to see the best player in the world play for our favorite team. After a few moments of looking in the mirror and realizing that the day had finally come, we quickly got dressed and headed to the bus stop across the street. After anxiously waiting, we got on the bus. When we arrived, it felt surreal. The stadium itself was massive, and since we had never been to a stadium larger than the U of I’s football stadium, it was a humbling fixture to stand in front of. The surrounding parking area was chock-full of supporters blasting music and cooking food and the air was filled with excitement and anticipation. In the blink of an eye, the gates opened and people started flooding into the stadium, and soon enough, the g

On sleepwalking

For the last few years, I have had rare (my parents see it once every 3 or 4 months) and extremely insignificant sleepwalking episodes. I walk around the second floor a few times and eventually make it back to bed. If one of my parents see me walking the second floor late at night, they issue the quick and easy sleepwalking test: “Hey Kev, are you sleepwalking?” If I say “no,” they know I’m not sleepwalking, but if I respond with unidentifiable mumbles, they escort me back to bed. Up until recently, from what my parents have seen, the most advanced task I have done is traverse the hallways, possibly holding a pillow and get a drink. A few weeks ago, I started having more peculiar sleepwalking bouts. On the second week of school, while sleepwalking, I turned on the lights to my room, took off and folded my pajamas, put on an outfit (surprisingly, one which matched and worked well aesthetically), charged my phone and go back in bed. This weekend, my parents saw me sleepwalking on